MJH: So what is the function of the word "essentialize"? Why
is it so bad to essentialize?
KAS: Essentializing is considered evil in cultural theory because
it presupposes or implies a biological, inherent, innate, somehow natural,
or inevitable notion of identity or personhood or even culture.
MJH: So if I say race has been incredibly important in American
constitutional history, am I essentializing?
KAS: See, that's the catch—it's difficult to discuss something
without making it an issue. And once we're talking about it, it's being
reiterated and further entrenched. The scary thing is that essentialism
seems to always be ready to recuperate itself as the master explainer.
I guess it's context that's really important—who's saying what about what
and for what reason. But how can you distinguish between a discussion that
has a particular political motivation or ideology and a discussion that
has another—they both appear in form to be naming and treating a particular
problem. Like the Supreme Court now—if they really are trying to construct
an environment that will be more conducive to racial justice, their motivation
isn't at fault, it's their technique.
MJH: So let's take it out of the particular moment. In 1905 somebody
says that if you, in discussion of freedom of contract, talk about large
corporations versus small or individual laborers, you are politicizing
the law. You are indeed essentializing the law. How do we then identify
the political motivation of anybody who has a methodological critique of
the other party's mode of thought? The answer is, we can't always be sure,
but one of the things that cultural studies helps us do is understand that
through a kind of holistic placing of the seemingly apolitical statement
in the context of the society, you might be able to come to the conclusion
that an anti-essentialist argument in favor of freedom of contract has nothing
other than protecting corporations in mind.
Or you might say, not that these people had as their motivation the
protection of corporations, these people just wanted to relive an earlier
world in which it was individual A versus individual B, and they couldn't
bear to take account of the cognitive dissonance that including a corporation
in their analysis would require. Is that conservative? Only cultural studies
can help us understand that blocking the noncomparable character of corporations
and individuals is a form of political denial. Likewise in the present
situation.
One can never, in a vacuum, identify an argument about methodology or
form as an argument about substance or politics. It's only by putting it
into an incredibly nuanced and contextual moment that you can entertain
the thought. You can never prove it in the form of formal logic. You can
only suggest it through the usual processes of good interpretation. So
that's the answer, it seems to me.
KAS: Do you think that the concept of originalism in constitutional
law is connected to what we're talking about?
MJH: Well, originalism says we should interpret the constitution
according to the original intent of the phrase. In constitutional law of
the last twenty years, it has been identified
with a Reagan/Meese/anti-abortion/overrule Roe v. Wade/ Bork position.
But it needn't be. There was a period when people went back
to the Civil War amendments to make originalist arguments for an expansive,
pro-protection of blacks notion of the Fourteenth Amendment. So originalism
doesn't have any necessary political spin, though it usually is deployed
by people with a certain kind of fundamentalist, Mt. Sinai state of mind.
And those people tend to have political tendencies and characteristics
that we would identify as conservative. But when Justice Black said that
Congress shall make no law, it means Congress shall make no law. And he
derived an absolutist version of the First Amendment from that in his particular
historical moment; I think there is no question that he was taking a progressive,
emancipatory view of the constitution.
KAS: Because at the time he had a particular political project
in mind, and that project could be aligned with progressive thinking. But
this absolutist interpretation of the First Amendment has since taken on
some kind of conservatism that no longer would be considered—
MJH: Exactly. Just as freedom of contract in the hands of late
eighteenth-century thinkers like Adam Smith was basically an emancipatory,
antifeudal, antimercantilist conception that, by the end of the nineteenth
century in the Lochner court, became our reactionary, antiprogressive mode
of thinking. So too, we see the same point with the First Amendment. When
Justice Black was attempting to elaborate the Holmes/Brandeis First Amendment
position, the typical situation was of the state attempting to suppress
political dissenters who were weak and powerless.
By the time we come to the Rehnquist court, we see the corporation having
First Amendment rights to spend as much money as it wants. And in Buckley
v. Malayo we get a money-is-speech doctrine in which any attempt by government
to limit your campaign contributions is regarded as an infringement of
your First Amendment rights. The rich therefore have more First Amendment
rights than the poor. So, clearly, when you get to that issue or when you
get to the hate speech or pornography issues, the social significance of
the First Amendment takes on a much more profound, much different character
than before. Then when you get to the information superhighway and First
Amendment access to sources of information, which will consume First Amendment
jurisprudence for the next thirty or forty years, you get a different social
composition. And once more, Justice Black's absolutism may take on a different
characteristic.
KAS: So absolutism can work in some circumstances.
MJH: Absolutely.
KAS: Kind of like the political uses of essentialism, which have
been argued by different thinkers. The historical context is then the pivotal
factor.
MJH: Exactly.
|